Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Exploring a Critical Theory of politics

Prospectando uma Teoria Crítica da política

Prospección de una Teoría Crítica de la política

Abstract:

The question of the contemporary political relevance of Critical Theory points to a deeper problem: the fundamental relationship between Critical Theory and politics. Their relationship status has to be regarded as complicated. Politics, so a widespread judgement goes, has no place in the cosmos of Critical Theory: where the place for a theoretically reflected analysis of politics could or should be, so the repeatedly heard reproach (for example, Howard 2000Dick, Howard. 2000. Political theory, Critical Theory, and the place of the Frankfurt school. Critical Horizons 1(2): 271-280. https://doi.org/10.1163/156851600750133379.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1163/...
), there is a gap in the center of the historical “Frankfurt School” (Wiggershaus 1995Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1995. The Frankfurt school: Its history, theories and political significance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press., Jay 1973Jay, Martin. 1973. The dialectical imagination: a history of the Frankfurt school and the institute of social research, 1923-1950. Toronto: Little, Brown & Company.) around Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno. In the following, we do not merely want to attest another “politics deficit” to “classical” Critical Theory, but rather, on the one hand, to measure the exact relationship to the object of politics, and on the other hand, to take a look at the current state of theory, which proves to be quite diverse. To ask whether and how a Critical Theory of politics is possible today does not, however, mean merely reflecting on current developments. This important task, we are convinced, first needs a theoretical foundation in order to be able to exploit the full potential of the approach. Accordingly, it is necessary to explore how, under current circumstances, the classical programmatic of Critical Theory can be linked to politics. In order to shed light on the problems with which contemporary thinking about the possibility and form of a Critical Theory of politics is confronted, we will begin by addressing the question of the place of politics in Critical Theory and the politics of critical theorists in some detail, and outline five theoretical levels (theoricity, aspiration, programmatic, theoretical methodology, temporal core) and three major paths (deepening, reorientation and return) on the basis of current approaches subsequently.

Keywords:
Critical Theory; Frankfurt School; Political theory; Sociological theory; Politics

Resumo:

A questão da relevância política atual da Teoria Crítica aponta para um problema mais profundo: o da relação fundamental entre a Teoria Crítica e a política. O status de seu relacionamento deve ser considerado complicado. A política, diz um julgamento amplamente difundido, não tem lugar no cosmos da Teoria Crítica: ali onde poderia ou deveria estar o lugar para uma análise teoricamente refletida da política, segundo a reprovação repetidamente ouvida (por exemplo, Howard 2000Dick, Howard. 2000. Political theory, Critical Theory, and the place of the Frankfurt school. Critical Horizons 1(2): 271-280. https://doi.org/10.1163/156851600750133379.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1163/...
), ali há uma lacuna no centro da histórica “Escola de Frankfurt” (Wiggershaus 1995Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1995. The Frankfurt school: Its history, theories and political significance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.; Jay 1973Jay, Martin. 1973. The dialectical imagination: a history of the Frankfurt school and the institute of social research, 1923-1950. Toronto: Little, Brown & Company.) em torno de Max Horkheimer e Theodor W. Adorno. A seguir, não queremos apenas atestar outro “déficit de política” na Teoria Crítica “clássica”, mas sim, por um lado, medir a relação exata com o objeto da política e, por outro lado, lançar um olhar sobre o estado atual da teoria, que se mostra bastante diverso. Perguntar se e como uma Teoria Crítica da política é possível hoje porém não significa meramente refletir sobre os desenvolvimentos atuais. Estamos convencidos de que esta importante tarefa precisa primeiro de uma base teórica para poder explorar todo o potencial da abordagem. Nesse sentido, é necessário explorar como, nas atuais circunstâncias, a programática clássica da Teoria Crítica pode ser vinculada à política. Para lançar luz sobre os problemas com os quais o pensamento contemporâneo sobre a possibilidade e a forma de uma Teoria Crítica da política é confrontado, começaremos abordando com algum detalhe a questão do lugar da política na Teoria Crítica e a política dos teóricos críticos, para na sequência delinear cinco níveis teóricos (teoricidade, aspiração, programática, metodologia teórica, núcleo temporal) e três caminhos principais (aprofundamento, reorientação e retorno) com base em abordagens atuais.

Palavras-chave:
Teoria Crítica; Escola de Frankfurt; Teoria política; Teoria sociológica; Política

Resumen:

La cuestión de la relevancia política actual de la Teoría Crítica apunta a un problema más profundo: el de la relación fundamental entre la Teoría Crítica y la política. El status de su relación debe considerarse complicado. La política, dice un juicio ampliamente sostenido, no tiene lugar en el cosmos de la Teoría Crítica: allí donde podría o debería ser el lugar para un análisis teóricamente reflejado de la política, según el reproche escuchado repetidamente (por ejemplo, Howard 2000Dick, Howard. 2000. Political theory, Critical Theory, and the place of the Frankfurt school. Critical Horizons 1(2): 271-280. https://doi.org/10.1163/156851600750133379.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1163/...
), hay un brecha en el corazón de la histórica “Escuela de Frankfurt” (Wiggershaus 1995Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1995. The Frankfurt school: Its history, theories and political significance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.; Jay 1973Jay, Martin. 1973. The dialectical imagination: a history of the Frankfurt school and the institute of social research, 1923-1950. Toronto: Little, Brown & Company.) alrededor de Max Horkheimer y Theodor W. Adorno. A continuación, no queremos simplemente apuntar otro “déficit de política” en la Teoría Crítica “clásica”, sino, por un lado, medir la relación exacta con el objeto de la política y, por otro lado, echar un vistazo en el estado actual de la teoría, que resulta ser bastante diferente. Sin embargo, preguntar si y cómo es posible una Teoría Crítica de la política hoy no significa simplemente reflexionar sobre los desarrollos actuales. Estamos convencidos de que esta importante tarea necesita primero una base teórica para poder explotar todo el potencial del enfoque. En este sentido, es necesario explorar cómo, en las circunstancias actuales, la programática clásica de la Teoría Crítica puede vincularse a la política. Para arrojar luz sobre los problemas con los que se enfrenta el pensamiento contemporáneo sobre la posibilidad y la forma de una Teoría Crítica de la política, comenzaremos por abordar con cierto detalle la cuestión del lugar de la política en la Teoría Crítica y la política de los teóricos críticos, para luego delinear cinco niveles teóricos (teorecidad, aspiración, programática, metodología teórica, núcleo temporal) y tres caminos principales (profundización, reorientación y retorno) basados en enfoques actuales.

Palabras clave:
Teoría Crítica; Escuela de Frankfurt; Teoría política; Teoría sociológica; Política

The place of politics in Critical Theory3 3 This article develops further the thoughts we originally laid out in the introduction to our volume Kritische Theorie der Politik published in German (Bohmann and Sörensen 2019). However, while there we focus primarily on the collected contributions, here we generalize our basic perspective and refer to a wider array of English-language publications.

The world is mad and it will remain so. - Max Horkheimer in Adorno and Horkheimer 2019 Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto. London: Verso. , 26 If you want to see a demonstration of what is meant by dialectic, by social dialectic, in a very simple model, then such a definition of the nature of the political is probably the best paradigm one could find - Adorno 2019 Adorno, Theodor W. 2019. Philosophical elements of a theory of society. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. , 39

As is well known, the label Critical Theory was first and significantly coined by Max Horkheimer in his essay Traditional and critical theory published in 1937 (Horkheimer 1972Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Critical Theory: Selected essays. New York: Continuum.). This essay is to be understood as a continuation of his 1931 inaugural lecture as director of the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt am Main, in which he developed an interdisciplinary and empirically-socially informed program of a social philosophy inspired by Hegel, Marx, and Nietzsche. Horkheimer defined the subject matter of this philosophy quite broadly:

Its ultimate aim is the philosophical interpretation of the vicissitudes of human fate - the fate of humans not as mere individuals, however, but as members of a community. It is thus above all concerned with phenomena that can only be understood in the context of human social life: with the state, law, economy, religion - in short, with the entire material and intellectual culture of humanity. (Horkheimer 1993Horkheimer, Max. 1993. Between philosophy and social science: Selected early writings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press., 425).

This broad definition is logical insofar as the work of the Institute for Social Research, as also formulated by Horkheimer in the preface to the first issue of the in-house Journal of Social Research (Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung), aims at a theory of contemporary society as a whole. Instead of falling prey to the prevailing division of labor into individual disciplines, according to Horkheimer, it is important to elaborate a discipline-integrative approach, since only such an approach is capable of grasping, understanding, and criticizing society in its totality. While state and law, as well as the associated disciplines, were still addressed in the inaugural lecture of 1931 as subject areas and components of a project of “Critical Theory”, state, law and political science are no longer explicitly mentioned in the aforementioned preface to the Journal of Social Research of 1932 - unlike philosophy, sociology, (social) psychology, economics and history.4 4 To our knowledge, the famous first preface of the Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung is still not translated into English. In this (implicit) exclusion of approaches from political science and governmental science, an orientation of the Critical Theory project already seems to have been established, which, as mentioned at the beginning, has also been diagnosed many times and is noticeable in the lack of an independent subject of “politics” in overview works (Gordon, Hammer and Honneth 2020Gordon, Peter E., Hammer Espen, and Axel Honneth, eds. 2020. The Routledge companion to the Frankfurt school. London: Routledge.). Such assessments were flanked by accusations of political abstinence against the representatives of the so-called first generation of Critical Theory, which found their most prominent expression in Georg Lukács’ aperçu of the “Grand Hotel Abyss”, to which the left-wing intelligentsia had retreated and from which the decline of the world could be analysed, but not fought politically or even averted (Jeffries 2016Jeffries, Stuart. 2016. Grand hotel abyss: the lives of the Frankfurt school. London: Verso .).

The place of politics in Critical Theory thus seems to be a blank space in several respects. This diagnosis, however, is based on reductions that do not do justice to the specific layout of Critical Theory. Insofar as the specific form of Critical Theory as a dialectical theoretical project also suggests a dialectical understanding of politics, which necessarily also entails contradictory conclusions, attitudes and consequences in dealing with and thinking about the political, we believe it would be more accurate to speak of constellations of ambivalence. These sometimes manifest themselves in the form of divergent positions within the discussion context of the “Frankfurt School”, but sometimes also within the work of a single protagonist alone. In the following, we will attempt to demonstrate this briefly with a view to the level of practical politics or politics of theory on the one hand, and the level of a theory of politics on the other.

The politics of Critical Theory and Critical Theorists

People want us far more outspoken. […] Our style must reveal what we think should happen. - Max Horkheimer in Adorno and Horkheimer 2019 Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto. London: Verso. , 42)

The establishment of the Institute for Social Research in 1923 was already a highly political affair. Founder and major patron Felix Weil, an Argentine-born Marxist and son of a wealthy grain merchant, was acutely politically motivated and sought contact with practical politics. His vision was a scientific, decidedly Marxist institute that would help guide the political struggles of the day. At the same time, the endowed institute itself was virtually foisted on the then actually conservative Frankfurt University through skillful political action, as it were as a “Trojan horse”. Thus the programmatic speech at the opening of the institute in 1924 by the first director Carl Grünberg, in which he unequivocally declared his Marxist orientation, which had hitherto been veiled in official matters, caused great irritation on the part of the university authorities. However, this origin did not have a lasting effect on the politics of the Critical Theorists. Not least for historical reasons, their development took a different direction. Thus, numerous theoretical reservations are increasingly formulated concerning the fundamental possibility of action aimed at overcoming domination in a totally “administered world” (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of enlightenment. Philosophical fragments. Stanford: Stanford University Press., xi). At the latest with the appearance of the Dialectic of Enlightenment, such a pessimism seems to unfold that all politics seems impossible or hopelessly corrupted. Adorno formulates this later in an aphorism of the Minima Moralia in the following way: “Society is integral, before it ever becomes ruled as totalitarian. Its organization encompasses even those who feud against it, and normalizes their consciousness.” (Adorno 2005Adorno, Theodor W. 2005. Minima moralia: Reflections on a damaged life. London/New York: Verso., 206). In view of this, the radical detachment from political events seems consistent. The resigned view of the possibilities of emancipatory politics under the conditions of liberal-capitalist representative democracies can also be found in Herbert Marcuse, the institute member often perceived as the most political proponent of the first generation, when he states in 1969: “The democratic process organized by this structure is discredited to such an extent that no part of it can be extracted which is not contaminated.” (Marcuse 1969Marcuse, Herbert. 1969. An essay on liberation. Boston: Beacon Press., 63). The “Great Refusal” he had already propagated the year before (Marcuse 1964Marcuse, Herbert. 1964. One-dimensional man: studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society. Boston: Beacon Press., see also Lamas et al. 2017Lamas, Andrew T., Wolfson, Todd, and Peter N. Funke, eds. 2017. The great refusal: Herbert Marcuse and contemporary social movements. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.) indeed seems the only logical reaction in this context. Nonetheless, as various studies have convincingly elaborated, especially with regard to Adorno, the accusation of a distanced-resigned retreat into the ivory tower is untenable if only because it ignores the practical-political engagement of central protagonists (Laudani 2013Laudani, Raffaele, ed. 2013. Secret reports on Nazi Germany: The Frankfurt school contribution to the war effort. Princeton: Princeton University Press.; Marotti 2016; Heins 2012Heins, Volker M. 2012. Saying things that hurt: Adorno as educator. Thesis Eleven 110 (1): 68-82. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0725513612450498.). This brings to light an ambivalence that was very clear to Adorno himself: “Whoever puts forward proposals easily makes himself into an accomplice. [...] A purist attitude, however, that refrains from intervening likewise reinforces that from which it timorously recoils.” (Adorno 1998aAdorno, Theodor W. 1998a. Interventions. Nine Critical Models. In Critical models: Interventions and catchwords, 1-122. New York: Columbia University Press., 3).

Similarly, an ambivalence can also be observed with regard to the political status of theory or theoretical work itself. If one follows Leo Löwenthal’s determination, then Marcuse’s “Great Refusal” is also constitutive for the theoretical project of Critical Theory itself: “Well, it is exactly the negative that was the positive: this consciousness of not going along, the refusal. The essence of Critical Theory is really the inexorable analysis of what is.” (Löwenthal in Dubiel 1981Dubiel, Helmut. 1981. The origins of Critical Theory: An interview with Leo Lowenthal. TELOS 49: 141-154. https://doi.org/10.3817/0981049141.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.3817/...
, 146). Unlike with regard to politics and political action in the everyday language sense, however, refusal in the context of theorizing does not stand for cutting one’s ties to the world. To see oneself as “collaborators of the negative phase of the dialectical process” (ibid.) does not mean to understand one’s own theory production as apolitical or to commit oneself to aversion from the world. Rather, Critical Theory is based on an understanding of the relationship between theory and practice, according to which not only “practice is a source of power for theory,” but also “theory becomes a transformative and practical productive force.” (Adorno 1998bAdorno, Theodor W. 1998b. Marginalia to Theory and Praxis. In Critical models: Interventions and catchwords, 259-278. New York: Columbia University Press., 278 and 264). In this respect, the theoretical work of the circle around Horkheimer and Adorno was always understood by the participants themselves - even in the most pessimistic moments - also as a political intervention with an emancipatory concern. The goal was the continuation of Marx’s categorical imperative, “to overthrow all relations in which man is a debased, enslaved, abandoned, despicable essence” (Marx and Engels 1975Marx, Karl, and Frederick Engels. 1975. Marx & Engels collected works. London: Lawrence & Wishart., 182). Critical Theory is thus always political theory insofar as it is partisan, borne by a “concern for the abolition of social injustice” (Horkheimer 1972Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Critical Theory: Selected essays. New York: Continuum., 242), and thus claims to be “the kind of theory which is an element in action leading to new social forms” (ibid., 216). However, it only becomes politically effective if an appropriate addressee can be found who allows the theory to prove itself in reality, to demonstrate its historical validity. The ambivalence thus does not exist with regard to the (claimed) politicity of Critical Theory, but with regard to the (possible) search for and dealing with potential addressees of the theory. On the one hand, the rather resigned variant of the “message in a bottle” is conceivable, which corresponds to the theoretical assumptions of a totally administered world and passively awaits possible future addressees. On the other hand, the rather activist-offensive variant can be considered, which Horkheimer formulates somewhat shirt-sleevedly but quite pointedly in a conversation with Adorno: “It is our cursed duty to marry thinking with right practice.” (Adorno and Horkheimer 2019Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto. London: Verso., 49). Adorno’s willingness to change his own style during his American exile in order to reach a broader democratic public could be interpreted as a step in this direction (Mariotti 2016Mariotti, Shannon L. 2016. Adorno and democracy: The American years. Lexington: University Press of Kentucky.).

Critical Theory of politics

Politics is both ideology and genuine reality. - Theodor W. Adorno in Adorno and Horkheimer 2019 Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto. London: Verso. , 26

But what about a systematic reflection on politics, what about a Critical Theory of politics itself? If one embarks on a search, the above-mentioned diagnoses of deficits seem to be quickly confirmed: The core of Critical Theory remains peculiarly devoid of reflections on politics. It is true that political questions and issues have been addressed time and again - one thinks, for example, of the Studies on Prejudice (Adorno et al. 1950Adorno, Theodor W., E. Frenkel-Brunswik, E. D. J., Levinson, and R. N. Sanford. 1950. The authoritarian personality. New York: Harper and Row.), which were concerned not least with the question of the extent to which and why democratic societies turn into dictatorial ones - but a systematic reflection on politics can ultimately only be found in the periphery of the tradition, namely in the work of Franz L. Neumann and Otto Kirchheimer.5 5 An exception is Horkheimer’s concise essay The Authoritarian State, first published in 1942 (Horkheimer 1973). Their studies can certainly be considered the most relevant explicitly political-theoretical approaches in the context of early Critical Theory, and both are still negotiated today as explicit guarantors of a Critical Theory of politics (Scheuerman 1997Scheuerman, William. 1997. Between the norm and the exception: the Frankfurt school and the rule of law. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press., Buchstein 2020Buchstein, Hubertus. 2020. Otto Kirchheimer and the Frankfurt school: Failed collaborations in the search for a Critical Theory of politics. New German Critique 47 (2): 81-106. http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/0094033X-8288139.
https://doi.org/http://dx.doi.org/10.121...
). Nonetheless, it should be emphasized that, significantly, Neumann resigned from the Institute for Social Research as early as 1942 in the aftermath of a controversy over the adequate classification and evaluation of the relationship between capitalism and fascism, and Kirchheimer also increasingly distanced himself both intellectually and personally (see Jay 1973Jay, Martin. 1973. The dialectical imagination: a history of the Frankfurt school and the institute of social research, 1923-1950. Toronto: Little, Brown & Company.; Wiggershaus 1995Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1995. The Frankfurt school: Its history, theories and political significance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.). Political theory, it seems, was unable to find a proper place in the “interdisciplinary materialism” of the Horkheimer circle (although there were early attempts to anchor Critical Theory in political theory, see Buchstein 2010Buchstein, Hubertus. 2010. From Critical Theory to political science: A.R.L. Gurland’s project of critical political science in postwar Germany. In Redescriptions: Yearbook of political thought, conceptual history and feminist theory 14, edited by Kari Palonen, 55-82. Münster: LIT Verlag.).

Seen in this light, then, the diagnoses of deficits are plausible, insofar as there is indeed a blank space in the work of the historical Frankfurt School in political science. How can this be explained? One (overly) simple interpretation might be: If resistant political action is obsolete or futile anyway, then theoretical reflection on politics certainly is. On closer examination, however, the situation is more complex, and it is possible that the blank space indicates in a serious way that the relationship between Critical Theory and politics or political theory is inherently problematic. The abstinence would then not be due to a resigned disinterest. Rather, we are possibly dealing here with a constellation of ambivalence that is based on the dialectical nature of the object itself - of politics.

Adorno’s reflection from his philosophical fragments on the connection between politics and ideology points in this direction:

On the one hand, the entire sphere of politics is certainly an aspect of ideology, that is to say, it seems as if the power struggles take place in the political sphere proper - the sphere of government, the sphere of legislation, the sphere of elections, in all these elements of political institutions - as if they were the matter itself, whereas they are epiphenomena over the real social process that carries them. It is especially difficult to see through this [...] because the things with which people are first confronted, apart from persons, are really political institutions that represent the social, and because it already demands a substantial and analytical process of abstraction to perceive the underlying play of social forces. [...] But, on the other hand, the sphere of politics as the sphere of seizing power, where it is quite possible for the entire fundamental conditions of life, especially the economic ones, to be decided, is after all a sphere, an ideology, that holds within it the potential to become something more, something different from mere ideology. (Adorno 2019Adorno, Theodor W. 2019. Philosophical elements of a theory of society. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press., 39).

Interestingly, such a dialectical understanding of politics also seems to reflect some of the central areas of tension in the self-understanding of Critical Theory (or the respective discourse). Thus, in a certain sense, it corresponds to the uncertainty regarding the so-called “prohibition of pictures” in relation to utopias, which, contrary to what is often circulated, can be considered quite controversial (Chrostowska 2019Chrostowska, S. D. 2019. Serious, not all that serious: Utopia beyond realism and normativity in contemporary Critical Theory. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 26 (2): 330-343. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12392.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/...
).6 6 Accordingly, there are also positive connections to utopian thinking in the field of Critical Theory, see especially Benhabib (1986) or most recently Chrostowska and Ingram (2017). This uncertainty probably emerges most succinctly in one of Adorno’s conversations with Ernst Bloch. While Adorno initially argues for “the prohibition of casting a picture of utopia actually for the sake of utopia” (Adorno in Bloch 1988Bloch, Ernst. 1988. Something’s missing: A discussion between Ernst Bloch and Theodor W. Adorno on the contradictions of utopian longing. In The utopian function of art and literature: Selected essays, edited by Ernst Bloch, 1-17. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press., 11), only a few pages later he recognizes something “very intricate” in the prohibition of pictures:

[T]his matter also has a very confounding aspect, for something terrible happens due to the fact that we are forbidden to cast a picture. To be precise, among that which should be definite, one imagines it to begin with as less definite the more it is stated only as something negative. But then - and this is probably even more frightening - the commandment against a concrete expression of utopia tends to defame the utopian consciousness and to engulf it. What is really important, however, is the will that it is different. (Adorno in Bloch 1988Bloch, Ernst. 1988. Something’s missing: A discussion between Ernst Bloch and Theodor W. Adorno on the contradictions of utopian longing. In The utopian function of art and literature: Selected essays, edited by Ernst Bloch, 1-17. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press., 12).

Equally related to politics - or the concept of politics - and equally characterized by an internal dialectical tension, is the idea of progress, which, at the latest with the Dialectic of Enlightenment, has a prominent status as an object of investigation to be problematized and which once again also drives the current debates in the field of Critical Theory (Allen 2016Allen, Amy. 2016. The end of progress: Decolonizing the normative foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press.; McCarthy 2012Heins, Volker M. 2012. Saying things that hurt: Adorno as educator. Thesis Eleven 110 (1): 68-82. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0725513612450498.).7 7 See also the recent special section Rethinking Progress in Constellations 28, n. 1 (2021). Also to be understood as dialectically constituted from the perspective of Critical Theory, as well as reaching into (or touched by) all three fields mentioned - politics, utopia, progress - is the topos of normativity. In concrete terms, this also concerns the normativity of Critical Theory itself, since according to its own basic epistemological assumptions it can neither be normative in a simple sense, nor simply non-normative. Even if not in name, we suspect, questions of utopia, progress, and normativity that are undoubtedly formative for Critical Theory always have questions of politics in the background. Quite certainly, at any rate, an at least implicit referential connection can be assumed.

It can therefore be concluded that there was a partly direct, partly mediated interest in a critical-theoretical penetration of politics. Finally, Adorno’s statement at the end of his 1963 lecture on the Problems of Moral Philosophy that “anything that we can call morality today merges into the question of the organization of the world. We might even say that the quest for the good life is the quest for the right form of politics” (Adorno 2000Adorno, Theodor W. 2000. Problems of Moral Philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University Press., 176). Although Adorno also doubts here “if indeed such a right form of politics lies within the realm of what can be achieved today” (ibid.), this can certainly be understood as a call to think about (good) politics in the spirit of Critical Theory.

Critical Theory of politics today: a panorama

Is the political question still relevant at a time when you cannot act politically? - Max Horkheimer in Adorno and Horkheimer 2019 Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto. London: Verso. , 25

Seen in this light, the project of a Critical Theory of politics within the original research context around Horkheimer and Adorno might present itself somewhat differently. Not as an unintentional project that was considered pointless, but rather as an unfinished task that has been postponed until further notice. If one disregards Kirchheimer’s and Neumann’s peripheral contributions, however, it is only much later, with the so-called “second generation”, that independent approaches to the theory of law and democracy come into play in the context of Critical Theory. Explicit reflections on political theory find their way into the (international) universe of Critical Theory in particular through the works on state, legal and democratic theory by Claus Offe (1984Offe, Claus. 1984. Contradictions of the welfare state. London: Hutchinson.) and, above all, Jürgen Habermas (1996Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.), albeit in highly different, sometimes more materialist-social-theoretical, sometimes more normative-idealist forms. While this undoubtedly represents an attempt to fill the gap or at least to make it accessible, the issue of politics ultimately remained largely under-thematized and the diversity of existing approaches were not systematically processed.

In the remaining part of our article, we would like to venture a rough overview, a preliminary and selective panorama. We do so in order to explore whether and how, under current circumstances, the “classical” programmatic of Critical Theory is being taken up from the perspective of political theory in the widest sense as well as in related disciplines, and in what form a Critical Theory of politics appears today. If one takes into account that there is hardly any agreement on what the unchanging essence of politics is supposed to be, with the determination of which everything external to it is set as non-political, then it is hardly surprising that quite different paths are taken. Those are sometimes separated by deep fault lines, but at the same time in some cases also show a multitude of ramifications. The project of a Critical Theory of politics should not, of course, be opposed to this inherently divergent diversity, since it is convinced in principle of the inconclusiveness of knowledge. The heterogeneity of the overview confirms, what perhaps the most significant determination of Critical Theory is in general: “There are no general criteria for judging the Critical Theory as a whole” (Horkheimer 1972Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Critical Theory: Selected essays. New York: Continuum., 242).

In order to be able to sound out a Critical Theory of politics today, we propose two explorative operations: First, we sketch out object-adequate possibilities of which different manifestations can be meant by “theory” at all. To this end, we identify five levels. We then propose to sort the confusing variety of current offers of a contemporary Critical Theory of politics into three basic paths. Both are done with exemplary references to current works available in English. As a matter of principle, the texts cited in each case are intended to illustrate a particular point - we do not wish to make reductive classifications of authors who all too often work on several levels and sometimes take different paths in different texts. On the whole, we are not merely being necessarily selective in our approach, but see it as imperative to formulate a clear caveat: The examples we have chosen come from European and Anglo-Saxon discourse contexts - we still have to owe an appropriate broadening of the panorama here.

Theory? What theory?

But eating roast goose is not the same thing as doing theory. - Max Horkheimer in Adorno and Horkheimer 2019 Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto. London: Verso. , 54)

Without claiming to be exhaustive, we propose five levels that we encounter more frequently in current debates about a contemporary Critical Theory. These are theoricity, aspiration, programmatic, theoretical methodology, and temporal core. Now to the individual levels:

(a) In sufficiently heterogeneous and diversified debate contexts such as the one we are interested in here, even the most elementary questions and apparent self-evident facts come under scrutiny: Is a Critical Theory something like “pure theory”? The alternative to theory, also in view of the dilemmas already mentioned that plagued the first generation of the Frankfurt School, would obviously be a retreat to singular political interventions that would have to be primarily strategic and interest-driven. The typical response, on the other hand, aims at mediation and might read thus: Theory as practice, theory as interference, theory as political intervention. In the cosmos of current Critical Theory with a political claim, this position can be found, for example, in Cooke (2020aCooke, Maeve. 2020a. Forever resistant? Adorno and radical transformation of society. In Companion to Adorno, edited by Peter E. Gordon, Espen Hammer, and Max Pensky, 583-600. New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell.) and Freyenhagen (2014Freyenhagen, Fabian. 2014. Adorno’s politics: Theory and praxis in Germany’s 1960s. Philosophy and Social Criticism 40 (9): 867-893. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453714545198.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177%...
), both following Adorno. Such a Critical Theory of politics is thus decidedly performative, or to be found with Marx “in a hand-to-hand fight”, and deliberately gets its hands dirty. Whether “beautiful purity” or “down in the dirt” - this question arises not only in political practice but also at the theoretical level itself, above all in the confrontation between “ideal theory” and “realism”, which has recently been much discussed in political theory (currently, for example, in Ferrara 2020Ferrara, Alessandro. 2020. Authority, legitimacy, and democracy: Narrowing the gap between normativism and realism. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 27 (4): 655-669. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12485.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/...
). In the field of interest here, a particularly sharp critique of ideal theory can be found in Geuss (2008Geuss, Raymond. 2008. Philosophy and real politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.). Conversely, realism itself is hardly attacked, but rather the meaningfulness of the distinction itself (e.g. Forst 2020Forst, Rainer. 2020. A Critical Theory of transnational (in-)justice: Realistic in the right way. In The Oxford handbook of global justice, edited by Thom Brooks, 451-472. Oxford: Oxford University Press.).

(b) As those remarks refer to the use of theorizing, which typically tends to lead away from a theory as an end in itself, nothing is said about its claim, about its formal scope. Löwenthal already admonished: Critical Theory is “a perspective, a common critical basic attitude toward all cultural phenomena without ever claiming to be a system” (Löwenthal in Dubiel 1981Dubiel, Helmut. 1981. The origins of Critical Theory: An interview with Leo Lowenthal. TELOS 49: 141-154. https://doi.org/10.3817/0981049141.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.3817/...
, 145). This is contrasted with the claim to understand society as a totality and to consciously explain it systematically. At one end of the scale, for instance, lies Rosa’s (2021Rosa, Hartmut. 2021. Resonance: A sociology of our relationship to the world. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.) comprehensive-general, in some cases even transcultural and transhistorical claim in his theory of resonance to be able to capture more or less all (or at least the essential) social pathologies of the present. In Honneth and Fraser (2003Honneth, Axel, and Nancy Fraser. 2003. Redistribution or recognition? A political-philosophical exchange. London: Verso.), in particular, one finds the specified claim to capture a particular historical social formation (such as present-day liberal-capitalist societies of the “West”) in its totality. At the other end, i.e. that of the lowest range claim, are singular, particular-exemplary approaches that deliberately focus on a relatively narrowly limited subject matter. Recent examples of this, which explicitly operate as Critical Theory with a political dimension, include the reappraisals of the topics “Landscape Heritage” (Baird 2017Baird, Melissa F. 2017. Critical Theory and the anthropology of heritage landscapes. Gainesville: University Press of Florida.), “Third World Films” (Gabriel 2021Gabriel, Teshome H. 2021. Towards a Critical Theory of third world films. Black Camera 12 (2): 317-337. https://doi.org/10.2979/blackcamera.12.2.18.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.2979/...
), and the study of self-immolation in Turkish prisons (Bargu 2014Bargu, Banu. 2014. Starve and immolate: The politics of human weapons. New York: Columbia University Press.).

(c) But what about the programmatic nature of the theory? A revealing guiding difference is already manifested in the use of a single letter: “Critical Theory of politics” with a capital C or a lowercase c? (Saar 2017Saar, Martin. 2017. Critical Theory and critical theories. Philosophy & Social Criticism 43 (3): 298-299. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453716676349.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177%...
) As a rule, this marks whether one moves within the narrower tradition of the Frankfurt School or in the wider variety of critical approaches. At the same time, it can be used to express a programmatic decision that also recurs to a place, but no longer to a particular academic discipline: How should a Critical Theory of politics today relate to its classically reference object, the genius loci Frankfurt? Accordingly, “Frankfurt” is not only a place, but also a cipher for a traditional context. In the foreground of corresponding works, however, is usually less explicitly this debate, but rather implicit programmatics, in which the authors performatively present which thematic orientation of a critical theory of politics (or the Critical Theory of politics) would be appropriate or desirable. Naturally, the programmatic approaches are sometimes competing, sometimes complementary. In terms of programmatics, Fraser (2013Fraser, Nancy. 2013. Fortunes of feminism: From state-managed capitalism to neoliberal crisis. London: Verso.) in particular argues in a decidedly intersectional way: a Critical Theory of politics today cannot avoid boldly taking up a combination of the relevant theoretical approaches and theoretical objects in the realm of social criticism - and for her, these are feminism, postcolonialism, ecology, and especially contemporary capitalism. Integrative grand theories are still lacking here, however.

(d) The various theoretical and programmatic ambitions make it necessary to approach the matter of “politics” (and in particular its normativity) also in terms of different theoretical methodologies, and to approach the concrete questions and objects in a specific form in each case. A basic distinction can be made according to the dominant mode, roughly sortable into the triad construction - reconstruction - deconstruction. A constructive approach is advocated by Forst (2011Forst, Rainer. 2011. The right to justification: elements of a constructivist theory of justice. Translated by Jeffrey Flynn. New York: Columbia University Press.), for example, who builds a right to justification as a critical standard, theorizing morality, reason, justice, and autonomy in particular. In a similar vein, Lafont (2020Lafont, Cristina. 2020. Democracy without shortcuts: A participatory conception of deliberative democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.) argues for a robust deliberative democracy. A reconstructive approach is strongly advocated by Honneth (2015Honneth, Axel. 2015. Freedom’s right: The social foundations of democratic life. New York: Columbia University Press.). He argues that normative standards would need to be recovered from our already lived-in legitimate laws and institutionally established practices. In this case, he is concerned with the value of freedom. The reconstructive tradition, strongly advanced by Habermas (1975Habermas, Jürgen. 1975. Towards a reconstruction of historical materialism. Theory and Society 2: 287-300. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00212739.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1007/...
, 1996Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.), is found throughout Honneth’s work, especially in his influential and widely advanced theory of recognition (Honneth 1996Honneth, Axel . 1996. The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.). A deconstructive approach is typically propagated either where common interests are seen with an overall philosophy of deconstructionism as represented by Jacques Derrida and fellow campaigners (Zima 2002Zima, Peter. 2002. Deconstruction and Critical Theory. London: Continuum.), or where the uncovering of unexpected effects of power and subordination is sought (Allen 2007Allen, Amy. 2007. The politics of our selves: Power, autonomy and gender in contemporary critical theory. New York: Columbia University Press.). Beyond these broad approaches, there is also a more frequent addressing of “crises” in terms of theoretical methodology (esp. Fraser 2013Fraser, Nancy. 2013. Fortunes of feminism: From state-managed capitalism to neoliberal crisis. London: Verso.; 2017Fraser, Nancy. 2017. Why two Karls are better than one: Integrating Polanyi and Marx in a critical theory of the current crisis. Working Paper DFG-Kollegforscher_innengruppe Postwachstumsgesellschaften, no. 1/2017. Jena: Friedrich-Schiller-University Jena.), as well as references to more precise methodologies such as “ideology critique” (Geuss 1981) or “genealogy” (Owen 2002) - a clear theoretical-methodological fixation thus does not seem to have established itself.

(e) One of the essential features of a theory with Frankfurt provenance is not least the postulate that every theory in its emergence, development and validity necessarily contains a temporal core, as Adorno and Horkheimer note in the preface to the Dialectic of Enlightenment. Accordingly, Fraser (1985Fraser, Nancy. 1985. What’s critical about Critical Theory? New German Critique 35: 97-131.), for instance, fundamentally recurs to Marx’s 1843 dictum of the “self-clarification [...] of the struggles and wishes of the age” (Marx 1975Marx, Karl . 1975. Letter to A. Ruge, September 1843. In Early writings, edited by Quintin Hoare. New York: Vintage Books., 209) in order to fathom what is critical about Critical Theory. “Theory” thus becomes precisely not an entity that is as universalist as possible, but a historically embedded instance that reflects on its own conditions and applications. The present-day relevance of a Critical Theory of politics is thus not a matter of course, but must be seen as a constant, demanding and always fallible task. It must prove itself in particular by addressing both contemporary political issues and contemporary problems. From this perspective, those include, for instance, poverty (Ingram 2018Ingram, David. 2018. World crisis and underdevelopment: A Critical Theory of poverty, agency, and coercion. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.), digitalization (Berry 2014Berry, David M. 2014. Critical Theory and the digital. London: Bloomsbury.), the European Union (Outhwaite 2012Outhwaite, William. 2012. Critical Theory and contemporary Europe. New York: Continuum.), climate change (Cooke 2020bCooke, Maeve. 2020b. Ethics and politics in the anthropocene. Philosophy & Social Criticism 46 (10): 1167-1181. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453720903491.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177%...
), property and possession (von Redecker 2020Redecker, Eva von. 2020. Ownership’s Shadow: Neoauthoritarianism as Defense of Phantom Possession. Critical Times 3 (1): 33-67. https://doi.org/10.1215/26410478-8189849.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1215/...
), racism (McCarthy 2012Heins, Volker M. 2012. Saying things that hurt: Adorno as educator. Thesis Eleven 110 (1): 68-82. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0725513612450498.), antisemitism (Rensmann 2017Rensmann, Lars. 2017. The politics of unreason: The Frankfurt School and the origins of antisemitism. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.), human rights (Benhabib 2011Benhabib, Seyla. 2011. Dignity in adversity: human rights in troubled times. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.), secularization (Lara 2013Maria, Pia. L. 2013. The disclosure of politics: Struggles over the semantics of secularization. New York: Columbia University Press.), civil disobedience (Celikates 2016Celikates, Robin. 2016. Rethinking civil disobedience as a practice of contestation - beyond the liberal paradigm. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 23 (1): 37-45. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12216.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/...
), legal revolutions (Brunkhorst 2014Brunkhorst, Hauke. 2014. Critical Theory of legal revolutions - evolutionary perspectives. London: Bloomsbury.), postcolonialism and imperialism (Kerner 2018Kerner, Ina. 2018. Postcolonial theories as global critical theories. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 25 (4): 614-628. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12346.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/...
), neoliberalism and right-wing populism (Brown 2019Brown, Wendy. 2019. In the ruins of neoliberalism: the rise of antidemocratic politics in the west. New York: Columbia University Press.), or untruth in politics (Vogelmann 2020Vogelmann, Frieder. 2020. Critical Theory and political epistemology: Six theses on untruth in politics. Azimuth: Philosophical Coordinates in Modern and Contemporary Age 16: 89-102.).

Constellations: confidants, elective affinities, adversaries

Simply to utter the words ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ is to form an alliance with [...] Mao Zedong. - Max Horkheimer in Adorno and Horkheimer 2019 Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto. London: Verso. , 39

How can, should or must the rich tradition of Frankfurt Critical Theory be dealt with in view of today’s political challenges - despite or because of its original constellation of political ambivalence? If one looks at relevant works that can plausibly be counted among the field of a Critical Theory of politics, the impression is that there can hardly be any question of a gap, as was perhaps the case historically. At the same time, however, there is not one answer that has prevailed, or one systematic theory that takes up all the relevant questions, or even one clearly identifiable academic discipline. Rather, we are dealing with a multifaceted diversity of contributions that is not always easy to keep track of. In order to sort out this field in a simplifying way and to make rough lines recognizable, we propose to identify three major paths of a contemporary Critical Theory of politics:

(1) A deepening of the direction taken by the second generation of the Frankfurt School in the second half of the twentieth century; this means following up on the great philosopher Jürgen Habermas (esp. 1996Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.; 1999Habermas, Jürgen. 1999. The inclusion of the other: studies in political theory. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.), who, through his turn in communication theory, strongly oriented Critical Theory in the direction of constructivist justice theory, deliberative democratic theory and liberal political theory, and thus achieved discourse sovereignty for the newer Critical Theory. (2) A reorientation, i.e. a change of course towards new theoretical shores; this means that a continuation of the emancipative intentions of Critical Theory today can only be regarded as meaningful and appropriate if the orientation is substantially changed or incorporates such Critical Theory elements that clearly lie beyond the Frankfurt School. (3) A return to original but seemingly outmoded or even forgotten motifs; that is, recommending or updating guarantors of the Frankfurt School, or even its theoretical precursors, for the solution of contemporary political questions.

The consideration of which concrete paths are to be taken for a Critical Theory of politics today is quite essentially at the same time the choice of who would be the right company on the way (or not): on whom from the tradition can one rely, which historical and current allies should be sought out, who are unreliable fellows to be eyed carefully, and with which figures should one rather change sides of the street? Theory is thus typically embodied in reference authors. These can be distinguished cum grano salis according to whether they belong to the “canon” of the Frankfurt School in the narrower sense (a), or (historically and factually) stand outside it (b). The choice of path and possible allies creates certain tensions of principle, which we will also briefly outline (c).

(a) With regard to the “canon”, a double caveat seems immediately appropriate: First, even a seemingly clear and comparatively overseeable canon is not exactly a self-evident object. In this section we refer only to the “Frankfurters” of the first generation, i.e. those researchers who worked at the Institute for Social Research in its founding years, and in its immediate environment. Historical predecessors - who certainly constitute a substantive “essence” of the Frankfurt School - will be addressed in the next section. Secondly, the majority of works on the (politics of the) Frankfurt School consist of works about it, rather than directly following it.

If one now turns one’s gaze resolutely to Frankfurt, it becomes apparent that Horkheimer’s definition of the essence and programmatic orientation seems to be the classic starting point par excellence for a Critical Theory of politics and is accordingly frequently cited. Nevertheless, Horkheimer is seldom used in detail and systematically for theorizing purposes; it usually remains with the reference to the distinction between “traditional” and Critical Theory (Horkheimer 1972Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Critical Theory: Selected essays. New York: Continuum.). The situation is different with the counterpart Adorno, who is clearly more frequently recommended as a central orientation figure (for example, Jameson 1990Jameson, Fredric. 1990. Late marxism: Adorno, or, the Persistence of the dialectic. London, New York: Verso. or Allen 2016Allen, Amy. 2016. The end of progress: Decolonizing the normative foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press.). Beyond Horkheimer and Adorno, the question of the canon arises most forcefully when one considers the actual history of the Frankfurt Institute for Social Research; here, however, we refrain from tracing the changing personal constellations and career paths within the Institute, and provisionally assume a kind of ideal canon, constituted only in retrospective and reception. With regard to a Critical Theory of politics, this includes several classical representatives, in particular Herbert Marcuse (Brown 2019Brown, Wendy. 2019. In the ruins of neoliberalism: the rise of antidemocratic politics in the west. New York: Columbia University Press.), Otto Kirchheimer and Franz Neumann (Scheuerman 1997Scheuerman, William. 1997. Between the norm and the exception: the Frankfurt school and the rule of law. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.) or Walter Benjamin (Loick 2018Loick, Daniel. 2018. A critique of sovereignty. London/New York: Rowman & Littlefield.). Erich Fromm, Leo Löwenthal or Friedrich Pollock, for example, play only a minor role, not to mention more marginal and lesser-known figures such as Karl-August Wittfogel or Henryk Grossmann.

(b) What about elective affinities outside the canon? We distinguish here between historical precursors and current theoretical offerings. In the historical category, it is particularly striking how numerous and continuous references are made to a kind of founding father who neither really has anything to do with Frankfurt, nor can even come close to passing as a contemporary of the school there: to Karl Marx. And this is no triviality. It is particularly pronounced in the work of Nancy Fraser (1985Fraser, Nancy. 1985. What’s critical about Critical Theory? New German Critique 35: 97-131.; 2014Fraser, Nancy. 2014. Behind Marx’s hidden abode. New Left Review 86: 55-72.; most recently Fraser and Jaeggi 2018Fraser, Nancy, and Rahel Jaeggi. 2018. Capitalism: a conversation in Critical Theory. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.), for example, that the very essence of Critical Theory goes back, or necessarily must go back, to Marx. But even with less emphatic invocations, it quickly becomes clear: Marx is a universally popular guarantor, and apparently largely uncontroversial through many camps (contrarily, however, esp. Cohen 1982). Since Critical Theory is not without reason also classified as Freudo-Marxism (which is not least evident in the influential studies on the authoritarian character, see Adorno 1950Adorno, Theodor W., E. Frenkel-Brunswik, E. D. J., Levinson, and R. N. Sanford. 1950. The authoritarian personality. New York: Harper and Row.), another precursor is obvious: Sigmund Freud, however, seems to divide opinions considerably more; Amy Allen’s Critique on the Couch (2021Allen, Amy. 2021. Critique on the couch. Why Critical Theory needs psychoanalysis. New York: Columbia University Press.; see also Bottici and Kühner 2012Bottici, Chiara, and Angela Kühner. 2012. Between psychoanalysis and political philosophy: Towards a Critical Theory of political myth. Critical Horizons 13 (1): 94-112. https://doi.org/10.1558/crit.v13i1.94.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1558/...
) currently makes a strong plea for a decisive role of psychoanalysis also in political questions. Other precursors vehemently recommended as foundations of a Critical Theory of politics are, first and foremost, Kant (Forst 2011Forst, Rainer. 2011. The right to justification: elements of a constructivist theory of justice. Translated by Jeffrey Flynn. New York: Columbia University Press.), Hegel (Honneth 2015Honneth, Axel. 2015. Freedom’s right: The social foundations of democratic life. New York: Columbia University Press.), and Nietzsche (Brown 2019Brown, Wendy. 2019. In the ruins of neoliberalism: the rise of antidemocratic politics in the west. New York: Columbia University Press.), and more rarely Rousseau (Ferrara 2017Ferrara, Alessandro. 2017. Rousseau and Critical Theory. Leiden: Brill.) - obviously not guarantors who can be followed simultaneously.

Among the desired newer and current allies and elective affinities, the diversification becomes even greater. We can only selectively list the numerous attempts at connection here, and, despite multiple ties, limit ourselves to only one exemplary reference in each case. But even so, a multifaceted panorama already emerges. Among the currently recommended guarantors are, for instance, the following exceedingly heterogeneous thinkers and approaches: Karl Polanyi (Fraser 2017Fraser, Nancy. 2017. Why two Karls are better than one: Integrating Polanyi and Marx in a critical theory of the current crisis. Working Paper DFG-Kollegforscher_innengruppe Postwachstumsgesellschaften, no. 1/2017. Jena: Friedrich-Schiller-University Jena.), Niklas Luhmann and systems theory (Schecter 2021Schecter, Darrow. 2021. Critical Theory and sociological theory: On late modernity and social statehood. Manchester: Manchester University Press.), Michel Foucault (Allen 2016Allen, Amy. 2016. The end of progress: Decolonizing the normative foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press.), Gilles Deleuze (Saar 2020aSaar, Martin. 2020a. Rethinking resistance: Critical Theory before and after Deleuze. Coils of the Serpent: Journal for the Study of Contemporary Power 5 (6): 68-80.), Hannah Arendt (Volk 2016Volk, Christian. 2016. Towards a Critical Theory of the Political: Hannah Arendt on Power and Critique. Philosophy & Social Criticism 42 (6): 549-75. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453715568921.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177/...
), feminism (Fraser 2013Fraser, Nancy. 2013. Fortunes of feminism: From state-managed capitalism to neoliberal crisis. London: Verso.), Jacques Derrida (Zima 2002Zima, Peter. 2002. Deconstruction and Critical Theory. London: Continuum.), Luc Boltanski and pragmatism (Celikates 2018Celikates, Robin. 2018. Critique as social practice: Critical Theory and social self-understanding. London and New York: Rowman & Littlefield.), John Rawls (Forst 2011Forst, Rainer. 2011. The right to justification: elements of a constructivist theory of justice. Translated by Jeffrey Flynn. New York: Columbia University Press.), Charles Taylor (Rosa 2021Rosa, Hartmut. 2021. Resonance: A sociology of our relationship to the world. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.), Judith Shklar (Heins 2019Heins, Volker M. 2019. “More modest and more political”: From the Frankfurt school to the liberalism of fear. In Between utopia and realism: The political thought of Judith N. Shklar, edited by Samantha Ashenden, and Andreas Hess, 179-197. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.), postcolonialism (Kerner 2018Kerner, Ina. 2018. Postcolonial theories as global critical theories. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 25 (4): 614-628. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12346.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/...
), John Dewey (Honneth 2017Honneth, Axel. 2017. The idea of socialism: Towards a renewal. London: Polity Press.), Enrique Dussel (Mendieta 2007Mendieta, Eduardo. 2007. Global fragments: globalizations, latinamericanisms, and Critical Theory. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.), or Judith Butler and queer theory (Allen 2007Allen, Amy. 2007. The politics of our selves: Power, autonomy and gender in contemporary critical theory. New York: Columbia University Press.).

(c) These divergent options lead us to controversies and antagonisms. If the Critical Theory of politics were a dogma, a sect, or a consensus program, it would seek the theoretical dispute only externally. However, it is far too diverse, too ambiguous, and too heterogeneous to do without considerable internal disagreement. In our opinion, however, the controversies are by no means a deficit, as they ultimately make the debate with the tradition and between the protagonists all the more spirited, which is beneficial for the level of the theoretical debate.

The main disputes over direction lie between the three paths of deepening, reorientation and return mentioned above. There seems to be fierce competition between the camp of deepening (1), which in the recent past has probably been most prominent in political theory, and the camp of reorientation (2), which urges theoretical readjustment and seeks to expose and repel the supposed heresies. The reorientation camp is dominated by a somewhat diffuse current which, on the basis of major overlaps, could probably best be described cum grano salis as the “post-camp” - with regard to Critical Theory, these are primarily post-structuralism (Saar 2020bSaar, Martin. 2020b. Critical Theory and poststructuralism. In The Routledge companion to the Frankfurt school, edited by Peter E. Gordon, Espen Hammer, andAxel Honneth , 323-335. London: Routledge.), post-Marxism (Garlitz and Zompetti 2021Garlitz, Dustin, and Joseph Zompetti. 2021. Critical Theory as post-marxism: The Frankfurt school and beyond. Educational Philosophy and Theory, ahead-of-print, 1-9. https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2021.1876669.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/...
) and post-colonialism (Ingram 2020Ingram, James. 2020. Critical Theory and postcolonialism. In The Routledge companion to the Frankfurt school, edited by Peter E. Gordon, Espen Hammer, andAxel Honneth , 500-513. London: Routledge.) - while the deepening camp could probably be put on the name with a broadly understood liberalism. This seems to us to be the dominant cleavage of a contemporary Critical Theory of politics. In particular, the questions invoked above about the (im-)possibility of normative standards, a clearly ascertainable progress, or even the translation of theory into political institutions play an essential role, with the post-camp typically taking the skeptical, and liberalism the emphatically affirmative position. Interestingly, an internal split can be seen in the return camp (3) - it is by no means uncontroversial which tradition should actually be recollected. Here, for example, references to mostly negativist positions following Adorno and Marcuse on the one hand, and rather institution-theoretical continuations with Neumann and Kirchheimer on the other, are opposed to each other. The same applies to orientations to Freud and Nietzsche, or to Kant and Hegel (in each case with considerable differences between them).

But here, too, the simplistically depicted situation is more complex; there are not simply two clear fronts irreconcilably opposed to each other. On the one hand, there are other options, such as the somewhat neo-Aristotelian or communitarian camp oriented towards the “good life” (e. g. Rosa 2021Rosa, Hartmut. 2021. Resonance: A sociology of our relationship to the world. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.). And on the other hand, there are both attempts at mediation (for instance between post-structuralism and the good life from the perspective of Critical Theory, see Cooke 2006Cooke, Maeve. 2006. Re-presenting the good society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.), and debates that not infrequently imply or at least enable fruitful exchange and rapprochement. Some time ago, for example, there was the “dialogue between genealogy and Critical Theory” (Ashenden and Owen 1998), respectively the debate between the followers of Foucault and Habermas, which was also conducted elsewhere. Most recently, the critical encounter between the paradigms of recognition and disagreement (Honneth and Rancière 2016Honneth, Axel, and Jacques Rancière. 2016. Recognition or disagreement: A critical encounter on the politics of freedom, equality, and identity. New York: Columbia University Press.) is one of the more prominent cases in this regard.8 8 See also the Special Issue Jacques Rancière and Critical Theory of the Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 27, no. 2 (2019). Overall, however, the debates, disputes, and controversies remain lively and unabatedly productive.

Final considerations

In this article, we have, on the one hand, elaborated in detail the fundamental constellation of ambivalence of the early Frankfurt School on politics. On the other hand, we wanted to show that there are a variety of promising approaches to a Critical Theory of politics today. To this end, we have listed selected elements of theorization, proposed a rough sorting on the basis of the three paths of deepening, reorientation and return, and tentatively named current reference authors. In doing so, we had relied on English-language literature, and moved very much within an “occidental” discourse of theory, especially US-American and German. Critical Theory, however, is not without time and place; it must, with Marx, strive for a self-understanding of the struggles and desires of the present and in the respective melees, in order to be able to contribute to more emancipation - in the field of politics this seems to be particularly called for. If these lines are published in a Brazilian journal, there is of course a need to say something about Brazil’s political conditions from the perspective of a Critical Theory. However, we do not want to presume to be able to do this adequately, being (self-)critically conscious though of the hegemonies beneath such apologies. It only remains for us to point out that the foundations are laid in the contributions in this special issue (or the bridges that can be crossed, e.g. the contribution of Ina Kerner). There are more than enough occasions, and it is not surprising that analyses of the current political situation begin with an invocation of Adorno (for example, Bittar 2021Bittar, Eduardo C. B. 2021. Challenges to democracy in the twenty-first century: The current situation of Brazil - new variations of the same dilemmas. Portuguese Studies 37 (1): 32-46. https://doi.org/10.5699/portstudies.37.1.0032.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.5699/...
). We look forward to a lively and fruitful debate, and hope for corresponding political actions.

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 1998a. Interventions. Nine Critical Models. In Critical models: Interventions and catchwords, 1-122. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Adorno, Theodor W. 1998b. Marginalia to Theory and Praxis. In Critical models: Interventions and catchwords, 259-278. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2000. Problems of Moral Philosophy Stanford: Stanford University Press.
  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2005. Minima moralia: Reflections on a damaged life London/New York: Verso.
  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2019. Philosophical elements of a theory of society Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
  • Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2019. Towards a new manifesto London: Verso.
  • Adorno, Theodor W., E. Frenkel-Brunswik, E. D. J., Levinson, and R. N. Sanford. 1950. The authoritarian personality New York: Harper and Row.
  • Allen, Amy. 2007. The politics of our selves: Power, autonomy and gender in contemporary critical theory New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Allen, Amy. 2016. The end of progress: Decolonizing the normative foundations of Critical Theory New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Allen, Amy. 2021. Critique on the couch. Why Critical Theory needs psychoanalysis New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Baird, Melissa F. 2017. Critical Theory and the anthropology of heritage landscapes Gainesville: University Press of Florida.
  • Bargu, Banu. 2014. Starve and immolate: The politics of human weapons New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Benhabib, Seyla. 1986. Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Benhabib, Seyla. 2011. Dignity in adversity: human rights in troubled times Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
  • Berry, David M. 2014. Critical Theory and the digital London: Bloomsbury.
  • Bittar, Eduardo C. B. 2021. Challenges to democracy in the twenty-first century: The current situation of Brazil - new variations of the same dilemmas. Portuguese Studies 37 (1): 32-46. https://doi.org/10.5699/portstudies.37.1.0032.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.5699/portstudies.37.1.0032
  • Bohmann, Ulf, and Paul Sörensen, eds. 2019. Kritische Theorie der Politik Berlin: Suhrkamp.
  • Bloch, Ernst. 1988. Something’s missing: A discussion between Ernst Bloch and Theodor W. Adorno on the contradictions of utopian longing. In The utopian function of art and literature: Selected essays, edited by Ernst Bloch, 1-17. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.
  • Bottici, Chiara, and Angela Kühner. 2012. Between psychoanalysis and political philosophy: Towards a Critical Theory of political myth. Critical Horizons 13 (1): 94-112. https://doi.org/10.1558/crit.v13i1.94.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1558/crit.v13i1.94
  • Brown, Wendy. 2019. In the ruins of neoliberalism: the rise of antidemocratic politics in the west New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Brunkhorst, Hauke. 2014. Critical Theory of legal revolutions - evolutionary perspectives London: Bloomsbury.
  • Buchstein, Hubertus. 2010. From Critical Theory to political science: A.R.L. Gurland’s project of critical political science in postwar Germany. In Redescriptions: Yearbook of political thought, conceptual history and feminist theory 14, edited by Kari Palonen, 55-82. Münster: LIT Verlag.
  • Buchstein, Hubertus. 2020. Otto Kirchheimer and the Frankfurt school: Failed collaborations in the search for a Critical Theory of politics. New German Critique 47 (2): 81-106. http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/0094033X-8288139.
    » https://doi.org/http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/0094033X-8288139
  • Celikates, Robin. 2016. Rethinking civil disobedience as a practice of contestation - beyond the liberal paradigm. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 23 (1): 37-45. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12216.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12216
  • Celikates, Robin. 2018. Critique as social practice: Critical Theory and social self-understanding London and New York: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Chrostowska, S. D. 2019. Serious, not all that serious: Utopia beyond realism and normativity in contemporary Critical Theory. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 26 (2): 330-343. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12392.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12392
  • Chrostowska, S. D., and James D. Ingram, eds. 2017. Political uses of utopia: New marxist, anarchist, and radical democratic perspectives New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Cooke, Maeve. 2006. Re-presenting the good society Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Cooke, Maeve. 2020a. Forever resistant? Adorno and radical transformation of society. In Companion to Adorno, edited by Peter E. Gordon, Espen Hammer, and Max Pensky, 583-600. New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Cooke, Maeve. 2020b. Ethics and politics in the anthropocene. Philosophy & Social Criticism 46 (10): 1167-1181. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453720903491.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453720903491
  • Dick, Howard. 2000. Political theory, Critical Theory, and the place of the Frankfurt school. Critical Horizons 1(2): 271-280. https://doi.org/10.1163/156851600750133379.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1163/156851600750133379
  • Dubiel, Helmut. 1981. The origins of Critical Theory: An interview with Leo Lowenthal. TELOS 49: 141-154. https://doi.org/10.3817/0981049141.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.3817/0981049141
  • Ferrara, Alessandro. 2017. Rousseau and Critical Theory Leiden: Brill.
  • Ferrara, Alessandro. 2020. Authority, legitimacy, and democracy: Narrowing the gap between normativism and realism. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 27 (4): 655-669. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12485.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12485
  • Forst, Rainer. 2011. The right to justification: elements of a constructivist theory of justice Translated by Jeffrey Flynn. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Forst, Rainer. 2020. A Critical Theory of transnational (in-)justice: Realistic in the right way. In The Oxford handbook of global justice, edited by Thom Brooks, 451-472. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Fraser, Nancy, and Rahel Jaeggi. 2018. Capitalism: a conversation in Critical Theory Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
  • Fraser, Nancy. 1985. What’s critical about Critical Theory? New German Critique 35: 97-131.
  • Fraser, Nancy. 2013. Fortunes of feminism: From state-managed capitalism to neoliberal crisis London: Verso.
  • Fraser, Nancy. 2014. Behind Marx’s hidden abode. New Left Review 86: 55-72.
  • Fraser, Nancy. 2017. Why two Karls are better than one: Integrating Polanyi and Marx in a critical theory of the current crisis Working Paper DFG-Kollegforscher_innengruppe Postwachstumsgesellschaften, no. 1/2017. Jena: Friedrich-Schiller-University Jena.
  • Freyenhagen, Fabian. 2014. Adorno’s politics: Theory and praxis in Germany’s 1960s. Philosophy and Social Criticism 40 (9): 867-893. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453714545198.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453714545198
  • Gabriel, Teshome H. 2021. Towards a Critical Theory of third world films. Black Camera 12 (2): 317-337. https://doi.org/10.2979/blackcamera.12.2.18.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.2979/blackcamera.12.2.18
  • Garlitz, Dustin, and Joseph Zompetti. 2021. Critical Theory as post-marxism: The Frankfurt school and beyond. Educational Philosophy and Theory, ahead-of-print, 1-9. https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2021.1876669.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2021.1876669
  • Honneth, Axel, and Jacques Rancière. 2016. Recognition or disagreement: A critical encounter on the politics of freedom, equality, and identity Ed. by Katja Genel and Jean-Philippe Deranty. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Geuss, Raymond. 2008. Philosophy and real politics Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Gordon, Peter E., Hammer Espen, and Axel Honneth, eds. 2020. The Routledge companion to the Frankfurt school London: Routledge.
  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1975. Towards a reconstruction of historical materialism. Theory and Society 2: 287-300. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00212739.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00212739
  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1999. The inclusion of the other: studies in political theory Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
  • Heins, Volker M. 2012. Saying things that hurt: Adorno as educator. Thesis Eleven 110 (1): 68-82. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0725513612450498.
  • Heins, Volker M. 2019. “More modest and more political”: From the Frankfurt school to the liberalism of fear. In Between utopia and realism: The political thought of Judith N. Shklar, edited by Samantha Ashenden, and Andreas Hess, 179-197. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
  • Honneth, Axel, and Jacques Rancière. 2016. Recognition or disagreement: A critical encounter on the politics of freedom, equality, and identity New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Honneth, Axel, and Nancy Fraser. 2003. Redistribution or recognition? A political-philosophical exchange London: Verso.
  • Honneth, Axel . 1996. The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Honneth, Axel. 2015. Freedom’s right: The social foundations of democratic life New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Honneth, Axel. 2017. The idea of socialism: Towards a renewal London: Polity Press.
  • Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of enlightenment. Philosophical fragments Stanford: Stanford University Press.
  • Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Critical Theory: Selected essays New York: Continuum.
  • Horkheimer, Max. 1973. The authoritarian state. TELOS 15: 3-20. https://doi.org/10.3817/0373015003.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.3817/0373015003
  • Horkheimer, Max. 1993. Between philosophy and social science: Selected early writings Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Ingram, David. 2018. World crisis and underdevelopment: A Critical Theory of poverty, agency, and coercion Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ingram, James. 2020. Critical Theory and postcolonialism. In The Routledge companion to the Frankfurt school, edited by Peter E. Gordon, Espen Hammer, andAxel Honneth , 500-513. London: Routledge.
  • Jameson, Fredric. 1990. Late marxism: Adorno, or, the Persistence of the dialectic London, New York: Verso.
  • Jay, Martin. 1973. The dialectical imagination: a history of the Frankfurt school and the institute of social research, 1923-1950 Toronto: Little, Brown & Company.
  • Jeffries, Stuart. 2016. Grand hotel abyss: the lives of the Frankfurt school London: Verso .
  • Kerner, Ina. 2018. Postcolonial theories as global critical theories. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory 25 (4): 614-628. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12346.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12346
  • Lafont, Cristina. 2020. Democracy without shortcuts: A participatory conception of deliberative democracy Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Lamas, Andrew T., Wolfson, Todd, and Peter N. Funke, eds. 2017. The great refusal: Herbert Marcuse and contemporary social movements Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
  • Laudani, Raffaele, ed. 2013. Secret reports on Nazi Germany: The Frankfurt school contribution to the war effort Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Loick, Daniel. 2018. A critique of sovereignty London/New York: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1964. One-dimensional man: studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society Boston: Beacon Press.
  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1969. An essay on liberation Boston: Beacon Press.
  • Maria, Pia. L. 2013. The disclosure of politics: Struggles over the semantics of secularization New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Mariotti, Shannon L. 2016. Adorno and democracy: The American years Lexington: University Press of Kentucky.
  • Marx, Karl, and Frederick Engels. 1975. Marx & Engels collected works London: Lawrence & Wishart.
  • Marx, Karl . 1975. Letter to A. Ruge, September 1843. In Early writings, edited by Quintin Hoare. New York: Vintage Books.
  • Mendieta, Eduardo. 2007. Global fragments: globalizations, latinamericanisms, and Critical Theory Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
  • Offe, Claus. 1984. Contradictions of the welfare state London: Hutchinson.
  • Outhwaite, William. 2012. Critical Theory and contemporary Europe New York: Continuum.
  • Redecker, Eva von. 2020. Ownership’s Shadow: Neoauthoritarianism as Defense of Phantom Possession. Critical Times 3 (1): 33-67. https://doi.org/10.1215/26410478-8189849.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1215/26410478-8189849
  • Rensmann, Lars. 2017. The politics of unreason: The Frankfurt School and the origins of antisemitism Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
  • Rosa, Hartmut. 2021. Resonance: A sociology of our relationship to the world Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
  • Saar, Martin. 2017. Critical Theory and critical theories. Philosophy & Social Criticism 43 (3): 298-299. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453716676349.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0191453716676349
  • Saar, Martin. 2020a. Rethinking resistance: Critical Theory before and after Deleuze. Coils of the Serpent: Journal for the Study of Contemporary Power 5 (6): 68-80.
  • Saar, Martin. 2020b. Critical Theory and poststructuralism. In The Routledge companion to the Frankfurt school, edited by Peter E. Gordon, Espen Hammer, andAxel Honneth , 323-335. London: Routledge.
  • Schecter, Darrow. 2021. Critical Theory and sociological theory: On late modernity and social statehood Manchester: Manchester University Press.
  • Scheuerman, William. 1997. Between the norm and the exception: the Frankfurt school and the rule of law Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Vogelmann, Frieder. 2020. Critical Theory and political epistemology: Six theses on untruth in politics. Azimuth: Philosophical Coordinates in Modern and Contemporary Age 16: 89-102.
  • Volk, Christian. 2016. Towards a Critical Theory of the Political: Hannah Arendt on Power and Critique. Philosophy & Social Criticism 42 (6): 549-75. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453715568921.
    » https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453715568921
  • Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1995. The Frankfurt school: Its history, theories and political significance Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Zima, Peter. 2002. Deconstruction and Critical Theory London: Continuum.
  • 3
    This article develops further the thoughts we originally laid out in the introduction to our volume Kritische Theorie der Politik published in German (Bohmann and Sörensen 2019Bohmann, Ulf, and Paul Sörensen, eds. 2019. Kritische Theorie der Politik. Berlin: Suhrkamp.). However, while there we focus primarily on the collected contributions, here we generalize our basic perspective and refer to a wider array of English-language publications.
  • 4
    To our knowledge, the famous first preface of the Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung is still not translated into English.
  • 5
    An exception is Horkheimer’s concise essay The Authoritarian State, first published in 1942 (Horkheimer 1973Horkheimer, Max. 1973. The authoritarian state. TELOS 15: 3-20. https://doi.org/10.3817/0373015003.
    https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.3817/...
    ).
  • 6
    Accordingly, there are also positive connections to utopian thinking in the field of Critical Theory, see especially Benhabib (1986Benhabib, Seyla. 1986. Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press.) or most recently Chrostowska and Ingram (2017Chrostowska, S. D., and James D. Ingram, eds. 2017. Political uses of utopia: New marxist, anarchist, and radical democratic perspectives. New York: Columbia University Press.).
  • 7
    See also the recent special section Rethinking Progress in Constellations 28, n. 1 (2021).
  • 8
    See also the Special Issue Jacques Rancière and Critical Theory of the Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 27, no. 2 (2019).
  • 9
    Os textos deste artigo foram conferidos pela Poá Comunicação e submetidos para validação do(s) editores antes da publicação.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    08 July 2022
  • Date of issue
    2022

History

  • Received
    16 Nov 2021
  • Accepted
    20 Nov 2021
  • Published
    20 June 2022
Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio Grande do Sul Av. Ipiranga, 6681 - Partenon, Cep: 90619-900, Tel: +55 51 3320 3681 - Porto Alegre - RS - Brazil
E-mail: civitas@pucrs.br